
Thursday, 30 May 2013
The Right to Die

Wednesday, 22 May 2013
Shirley Jackson's Lottery and Other Stories
Prompted by my
students’ reading of John Harris’s “The Survival Lottery” (see previous blog
post), I got hold of Shirley Jackson’s The
Lottery and Other Stories, published by Penguin. I had never read any of
Jackson’s stories or novels before, and in fact only knew about her from
Stephen King who has often praised her. And rightly so, as I know now. Without
ever explaining or commenting on the events that she narrates, Jackson makes
the ordinary appear uncanny and reveals the cruelty, the violence and the emptiness
that lurk below the thin surface of what we call civilization, not overcome or
even tamed, but merely hidden away or temporarily channeled into the
all-pervasive, stifling structures of oppression that regulate our lives and
that we think of as normal.

In “The Renegade” a
young family, the Walpoles, have just moved to the country and are still trying
to settle in when Mrs Walpole is being told by one of their new neighbours that
their dog, affectionately called Lady, has been seen chasing and killing
chickens. Within a couple of hours everyone in the little community knows about
it, and although Mrs Walpole apologises profusely and promises to make amends,
everyone she meets tells her that she needs to do something about the dog:
either kill her or make it impossible for her ever to kill a chicken again. Asking
her neighbours for advice, the suggestions she gets become increasingly cruel.
Nobody pays the slightest attention to the welfare of the dog or to the bond
that exists between her and the family – although even that bond, or the
reality or thickness of it, is quickly called into question: when the two
Walpole children come home from school, they already know all about it and
cheerfully announce to the dog that she will be shot or worse. A neighbour, “a
genial man who lived near the Walpoles and gave the children nickels and took
the boys fishing”, had told them they needed to get a collar for the dog,
hammer big thick nails all around inside it, put it around the dog’s neck, get
a long rope, fasten it to the collar, take her where there are chickens, turn
her loose, and then, when she gets really close, pull on the rope, hard, so
that the spikes cut her head off. Again, the children don’t find this prospect
frightening or at least alarming at all. Rather, they think it’s absolutely
hilarious. “They both began to laugh and Lady, looking from one to the other,
panted as though she were laughing too. Mrs. Walpole looked at them, at her two
children with their hard hands and their sunburned faces laughing together,
their dog with blood still on her legs laughing with them. She went to the
kitchen doorway to look outside at the cool green hills, the motion of the
apple tree in the soft afternoon breeze. ‘Cut your head right off,’ Jack was
saying. Everything was quiet and lovely in the sunlight, the peaceful sky, the
gentle line of the hills. Mrs. Walpole closed her eyes, suddenly feeling the
harsh hands pulling her down, the sharp points closing in on her throat.”

This year it is Tessie
Hutchinson, well-liked wife and mother of three, who is unlucky enough to draw
the losing ticket. Once it is clear that she’s the one, her friends and neighbours,
and with particular glee the children, including her own, take stones from the
ground and, without any hesitation and despite Tessie’s anguished cries of
protest, throw them at her until she is dead. “Tessie Hutchinson was in the
center of a cleared space by now, and she held her hands out desperately as the
villagers moved in on her. ‘It isn’t fair,’ she said. A stone hit her on the
side of the head. (...) ‘It isn’t fair, it isn’t right,’ Mrs. Hutchinson
screamed, and then they were upon her.”
There is no indication,
however, that Mrs. Hutchinson would have protested if somebody else had been
chosen. If one of her friends had had the bad fortune of losing the lottery,
she would have thrown stones with the others. It is only by being personally
affected that she comes to realise the wrongness of the whole procedure, or if
she herself doesn’t, then at least we do. It isn’t fair, it isn’t right, not
that this particular person has to die, but that someone is randomly picked to die. I almost wrote “for no good
reason”, but that would be a mistake, because it seems to me that the whole
point of this story is to show that even if there were some useful purpose to the whole procedure, even if it were,
say, true that the success of the harvest depended on the annual ritual
sacrifice of one of them, even then would it remain a terrible, nightmarish
thing to do. Something that can never be justified. And in that respect it is
exactly like Harris’s survival lottery. Certain things must not be done no
matter how useful they appear to be. Nobody should be sacrificed for the
alleged good of the community. An evil act remains an evil act even if someone
benefits from it. Utility is not the measure of all things.
Sunday, 12 May 2013
The Allure of the Number Game

The typical bioethicist
is rather fond of radical solutions. He dislikes waste, has no patience with what he sees as people’s squeamishness, and believes that we
should be rational about things,
which mostly means that we should rethink our morality, our established views
of right and wrong, if there is no other or better way to solve a problem
quickly and efficiently. Do you believe that people should have a say in what
happens to their bodies when they are dead? - But then they may not allow us to
use their organs, which we urgently need. To save lives! To help people! So we
really cannot afford letting those
organs go to waste, and that means we cannot afford allowing people to decide
for themselves whether they want to “donate” their organs or not. Do you
believe that organs should only be taken from dead people who no longer need
them? - But some who are still alive are in fact as good as dead, so that they
would not really miss those organs. And besides, we urgently need them now. We really cannot afford to wait
until people are completely dead. After all, there are people’s lives at stake here. Actually, come to
think about it, we cannot even afford to wait until people are almost dead. It
would be so much more efficient if we could just take the organs we need from
the living, if we could kill a few to save many others. It’s all for the
greater good. Yes, of course, killing people for their organs is currently
frowned upon, but hey, it doesn’t have to stay this way. Sometimes sacrifices
have to be made for the common good, and anyway, we may quickly get used to it
and see the error of our previous ways.
This is what the
Manchester-based philosopher John Harris suggested in a paper published almost
40 years ago (“The Survival Lottery”, Philosophy
50/ 191 (1975): 81-87), in which he proposed that we solve the problem of not
being able to procure enough spare organs to save the growing number of people
who need new organs to survive by establishing a lottery. Each of us is
assigned a number, and whenever there is a shortfall of organs, a number is
drawn and the lucky bastard whose number it is gets killed (or rather called
upon to “give his life”). All his organs can then be used to preserve the lives
of those who need them. This way a lot less people would have to die.
To me this is the stuff
that dystopian nightmares are made of. Yet when I put the question to my
students, asking them in an exam whether they thought that Harris’s survival
lottery was “a morally acceptable way to tackle organ shortage”, I once again found
that a majority of them did not only think that it was morally acceptable, but in fact that it was
clearly what was morally required.
They showed themselves quite convinced by Harris’s utilitarian reasoning and
the crucial assumption that there is no morally relevant difference between
killing and letting die, so that if we have to kill one to prevent two or
more people from dying, then that is exactly what we should do. The numbers
speak for themselves. They appear to have an enormous persuasive power. As one
student put it: “Such massive consequential benefits to society as a whole seem
to me to rather morally outshine the far rarer occasional acts of killing.” As
if the legalisation of “occasional acts of killing” by an agency of the state
could ever be justified. That is the kind of argument that Hitler and Stalin
must have used when they justified their policies before themselves and others.
It blindly follows the imperative of maximisation. And I think I get its
allure. It makes things so much easier. Who needs a conscience when we’ve got
numbers, right? But I’m still surprised, and also dismayed, by how easily people
can be persuaded to endorse inhuman practices and how willing they are to
believe that everybody is expendable and that to be treated solely as a means
to an end is perfectly all right, so that the state should have the power to
take our lives whenever it is deemed expedient. As another student put it: “As
utility is the maximisation of pleasure, then people can rightly be viewed as
interchangeable parts in a mechanism, designed to promote as much happiness as
possible.” Rightly! How can people be
so willing to give up their most basic rights, to see themselves as an
interchangeable part in a mechanism? We are all oil on the wheels of the great
utilitarian happiness machine. Is that really what we are or how we want to see
ourselves? And for whose sake really? Other people’s lives? But those other people
are just as expendable as we are. Surely there is a contradiction at the heart
of this terrifying proposal: human life is proclaimed to be so important that anything is acceptable to save it,
including the killing of a healthy, innocent and perfectly alive human being.
But by finding this acceptable we implicitly declare the life of that human
(and with it the life of any human)
for disposable. If the individual human life doesn’t count, then we don’t seem
to have a good reason to want to save it at all costs. Then we can just as well
let people die. The truth is that the reason why we think that we should save
people’s lives if we can is in fact the same reason that makes us (or, if we
were thinking straight, should make us) reject Harris’s proposal.
Sometimes I think that,
on the whole, applied ethics might be doing more harm than good, that more
often than not it doesn’t aid our moral thinking, but corrupts it. It makes the
unthinkable thinkable. I used to believe that this was an advantage. I’m not so
sure anymore.
Friday, 3 May 2013
Primo Levi on (Not) Understanding the Holocaust

Now, I’m not so sure
anymore, and the reason is that I have just read Primo Levi’s account of his
time in Auschwitz (If this Is a Man,
1947), and of his long journey home to his native Turin after the war had ended
(The Truce, 1963). In an afterword to
the Everyman edition of these two books, Levi gives answers to his readers’
questions. Asked about how the Nazis’ fanatical hatred of the Jews could be
explained, he emphasises the importance of not
explaining and not trying to
understand that hatred:

Levi contrasts
understanding with knowing. The latter is a duty, which includes knowing the
causes of what happened to make sure that it doesn’t happen again. But
understanding is more intimate, it bridges the reflective distance between the
subject and the object of understanding. By “understanding” the Holocaust we
would acknowledge it as a real human possibility, as something that is
understandable for humans to do. But it is important to reject this possibility,
to preserve an image of the human that positively excludes it. Humans ought
never to be able to do such things. Whoever shows himself capable of it (and
this may very well include us) has given up their humanity, and they have given
it up precisely because they have ceased to see and treat the other as human. We
become (or stay) human by treating other humans as humans.
How did he survive
Auschwitz, Levi is asked, and he replies: lots of luck, a desire to bear
witness to the events, and finally “the determination, which I stubbornly
preserved, to recognize always, even in the darkest days, in my companions and
in myself, men, not things, and thus to avoid that total humiliation and
demoralization which led so many to spiritual shipwreck.”
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)