“It’s lovely to live on
a raft. We had the sky, up there, all speckled with stars, and we used to lay
on our backs and look up at them, and discuss about whether they was made, or
only just happened - Jim he allowed they
was made, but I allowed they happened; I judged it would have took too long to
make so many. Jim said the moon could a laid them; well, that looked kind of
reasonable, so I didn’t say nothing against it, because I’ve seen a frog lay
most as many, so of course it could be done.”
Jim’s reasoning is
built firmly on experience: making a
thing takes time, and making so many copies of a thing as there are stars in
the sky would have taken an awful lot of time, so it is rather unlikely if not
downright impossible that anyone would have taken the trouble to do so. But laying, giving birth, is a process that takes
almost no time at all, at least that’s how it may appear to the casual
observer: at one moment there is nothing, and the next there is. It is not
quite happening, but not making either. Our parents haven’t made
us, but neither have we just happened. We have gradually come into existence,
in our secret hiding place, the maternal womb, before, at some point, we were
suddenly thrown into the world. Our parents have set the whole process that
eventually led to our existence in motion, but all the rest happened by itself,
although clearly following a plan, a plan that was not devised by our parents. Perhaps
the universe has come into existence in a similar way. Perhaps God didn’t make
the world either. Perhaps he (or rather she) gave birth to it. (I have to admit
I’m not entirely sure what that means, but I’m rather fond of the idea.)Wednesday, 20 November 2013
Huckleberry Finn on How the World Was Made (or Laid)
Reading Mark Twain’s The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn, I
came across the following intriguing passage (in chapter 19), in which Huck
tells the reader about a brief philosophical or rather cosmological argument he
had with his friend and companion, the runaway slave Jim.
Monday, 18 November 2013
Do Automatic Sweethearts Work?
A couple of weeks ago I
briefly discussed, prompted by David Levy’s treatment of the issue in his book Love and Sex with Robots, whether a
robot can be said to love a person if they say
they do and act as if they did. Today
I’d like to continue this discussion.

“The flaw was evident
when, as a case analogous to that of a godless universe, I thought of what I
called an ‘automatic sweetheart,’ meaning a soulless body which should be
absolutely indistinguishable from a spiritually animated maiden, laughing,
talking, blushing, nursing us, and performing all feminine offices as tactfully
and sweetly as if a soul were in her. Would any one regard her as a full
equivalent? Certainly not, and why? Because, framed as we are, our egoism
craves above all things inward sympathy and recognition, love and admiration.
The outward treatment is valued mainly as an expression, as a manifestation of
the accompanying consciousness believed in. Pragmatically, then, belief in the
automatic sweetheart would not work,
and in point of fact no one treats is as a serious hypothesis.”

When we occasionally
call a lover “soulless”, we do, according to Singer, in fact refer to a certain
(already observed or predicted) behaviour,
so if there is a difference between the soulful and the soulless it is a
difference in behaviour: “If I imagine myself come to believe that my mistress,
with all her loveliness, is really without soul, I cannot think what I should
mean by this if it be not that I fear her future conduct will not bear out my
expectations regarding her. Some trait or gesture, a mere tightening of the
lips, hardening of the eye, stifling of a yawn, one of those things we say are
rather felt than seen, would have raised in my mind the suspicion that she
might not to my fuller experience of her remain indistinguishable from a
spiritually minded maiden.” If the distinction between ‘soulless’ and ‘soulful’
means anything, then it is this. “Consciousness is not something inferred from
behavior; it is behavior.”
James’s point, of
course, was that we wouldn’t be happy
with a lover of whom we knew that
they didn’t really feel anything for us and that all their seemingly loving
actions deceive us to the extent that
they indicate some kind of emotional involvement on the part of our lover. Yet
Singer could respond that we might well be unhappy with an automatic
sweetheart, but that we really shouldn’t
be because to react like that is completely irrational, given that a real human
lover would do nothing different from the automatic one.
It is interesting,
though, to see how neatly Singer’s description of a “soulless” lover (where the
term can be meaningfully ascribed)
fits with the descriptions that we find in literature of equally unsatisfying
women and with the accompanying eulogies on the virtues of the artificial lover
(as, for example, in Ovid’s Pygmalion,
Hoffmann’s The Sandman, or Villiers’ The Future Eve). Once again, it is the
real human lover who is decried as soulless, the one that turns out not to be
completely reliable, completely with us, completely there for us. It is the
yawn that indicates the lack of soul, a less than interested gaze. That is the
danger that always exists when we risk getting involved with real human beings.
They might lose interest in us, might grow cold and unresponsive, might stop
loving us. If that is an indicator of soullessness, then each and every one of
us is soulless, and only an automatic sweetheart, one whose eyes will always
gaze lovingly at us and will never lose their shine, whose lips never tighten,
but are always soft and welcoming, and who will never have to stifle a yawn,
only such a one can be said to have a soul.
Thus it appears that the
effect of denying that there is any difference between a real person and a fake
person, between a real human lover and an automatic sweetheart, is that the
soulless becomes, or comes to be regarded as, the truly soulful, and the soulful the truly soulless.
Wednesday, 6 November 2013
E.T.A. Hoffmann's Olimpia
Here’s yet another tale
about a man’s erotic obsession with a female android, or automaton as it used
to be called at the time: E.T.A. Hoffmann’s “The Sandman”, which was first
published in 1817 as part of the story collection Nachtstücke (Night Pieces). It is the story of a young university
student called Nathanael who, haunted by the memory of a traumatic childhood
experience connected to his father’s death and a mysterious malevolent figure called
Coppelius whom as a child he used to identify with the monstrous, eye-stealing
Sandman, and who might or might not be real, gradually slides deeper and deeper
into madness and eventually throws himself off a tower and kills himself.
But before he does, he
becomes infatuated with what at first seems to be a beautiful young woman
called Olimpia, who appears to be the daughter of his neighbour (and professor),
but later turns out to be nothing but a cleverly constructed (moving and
talking) wooden doll. This might be evidence of his growing insanity or a
factor contributing to it, but in any case it is rather odd given that he seems
to be the only one who does not realize that there is something seriously wrong
with the object of his infatuation. Although Olimpia is so superbly crafted and
so life-like that when she is introduced to people at a ball, they do not
immediately recognise her as what she is, namely a machine, they all sense her
strangeness and want nothing to do with her. They find her “strangely stiff and
lacking in animation”, her eyes lifeless, as if they were blind (which they
are, of course), “as though her every movement were produced by some mechanism
like clockwork” (which it is). They believe her to be a “complete imbecile, who
plays music and sings “with the disagreeably perfect, soulless timing of a
machine”, as if “she was only pretending to be a living being”

The narrator describes Clara
as follows: “Clara had the vivid imagination of a cheerful, ingenuous,
child-like child, a deep heart filled with womanly tenderness, and a very
acute, discriminating mind. She was no friend to muddle-headed enthusiasts
(...) Many people accordingly criticized Clara for being cold, unresponsive,
and prosaic.” Although Nathanael is reported not to belong to those people, his
words and actions indicate that in fact he does. When it becomes clear to him
that she doesn’t believe in “the mystical doctrine of devils and evil forces”, Nathanael
blames her disbelief on her “cold and insensitive temperament”, and when she
persists in her gentle and loving attempts to talk some sense into him, he
accuses her of being a “lifeless automaton”.

When Nathanael
eventually learns the truth about Olimpia, that she is in fact merely a wooden
doll, he completely breaks apart:”Madness seized him with its red-hot claws and
entered his heart, tearing his mind to pieces.” And as the story of his fate
spreads, those who hear it, instead of congratulating themselves on their own
good sense, start doubting their own judgement and suddenly see robots lurking
in every corner and behind every human face: “In order to make quite sure that
they were not in love with wooden dolls, several lovers demanded that their
beloved should fail to keep time in singing and dancing, and that, when being
read aloud to, she should sew, knit, or play with her pug-dog; above all, the
beloved was required not merely to listen, but also, from time to time, to
speak in a manner that revealed genuine thought and feeling. The bonds between
some lovers thus became firmer and pleasanter; others quietly dissolved. ‘One
really can’t take the risk’, said some.”


In another of his
tales, “The Automata” (which may not have been translated into English),
Hoffmann has one of his characters express his disgust for all automata that
attempt to assume a human shape. He calls them “those true statues of a living
death or a dead life” (“diese wahren Standbilder eines lebendigen Todes oder
eines toten Lebens”). This sums up the ambiguity quite nicely.
Friday, 1 November 2013
Animal Nature Disgust in Ovid's Pygmalion

This
loss of shame is clearly understood as a decisive step in a process of
dehumanisation: a little more hardening, we are told, and they would be
indistinguishable from flint. (Compare this to Lord Ewald’s claim in Villiers
de l’Isle Adam’s The Future Eve that
Alicia has no “soul” because she is too earthly.) Appalled by so much female depravity,
Pygmalion decides (just as many centuries later Celia’s disillusioned lover in
Swift’s “Lady’s Dressing Room”) that he no longer wants to have anything to do
with women and is determined to stay a bachelor. Yet entirely happy with his
wifeless (read: sexless) existence he is not, because soon enough he carves a
statue that looks exactly like a woman and is so exceedingly lifelike that one has
the impression that she might move any second now and that it is only modesty
that keeps her from doing so. And Pygmalion falls in love with his own
creation. Here is, finally, the woman that he has been waiting for, that all
men (if we take Pygmalion to represent the male sex) have been waiting for: a
woman who knows how to behave properly and who is pure and free of all unseemly
desires and inclinations, and this purity and freedom makes her much superior
to all real women. In Pygmalion’s mind, the statue is actually more human than any real woman could ever be.
All real women are ultimately like the Propoetides: natural born sluts, and as
such less than human (less than what humans, or at least human females, should
be), more like stones, almost like living statues. The actual statue, on the
other hand, is as a woman should be. The statue, in its immaculate
ivory-whiteness is the true woman.

So
why is Pygmalion not disgusted by her? What is it about her that makes her so
different from all other women that he can accept her and even have sexual
intercourse with her without being repelled by her? It must have something to
do with the fact that she is not an ordinary woman, but a statue come alive,
and that she carries the modesty, the bashfulness of the inanimate thing, over
to her new existence. She doesn’t move on her own. She doesn’t follow her own
will. She has no own will. She is a perfect mirror of her lover’s desires, without
having any desires of her own that might threaten her purity. She lives only
for her lover, who is her one and only. He is, quite literally, her world. She
is a supposedly living woman, but without the flaws, a living paradox. She is perfect
and pure, but also perfectly usable, obedient and ready to serve her one and
only master. She does what she is told. She is the ideal woman, the Eve of the
Future, a precursor of today’s or tomorrow’s sexbots, a tailor-made,
always-willing, never-tiring sexual companion, a Stepford wife.
Isn’t
it odd how little our desires have changed over the last two thousand years?
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)