In
a very long and rich paper on “Meaningfulness and Time”, published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
84/2 (2012): 345-377, Antti Kauppinen defends what he calls the “Teleological View
of meaningfulness”. Meaningfulness is here understood as one of the two
properties that makes a life good for the one who leads it, the other one being
happiness (or pleasure). Both together constitute human well-being. Since
happiness (pleasure) and meaningfulness are distinct properties, a life can be
happy, but meaningless, and also unhappy, but meaningful. (N.B.: Although Kauppinen
is far from alone in distinguishing meaningfulness from happiness, there is something
odd about treating them as separate. People are, after all, not likely to be
happy and at the same time regard their life as meaningless. If they do regard their life as meaningless, feeling
that there is no real point to what they are doing, this usually means that
they are not happy. The apparent
pointlessness of their lives is what makes
them unhappy, or a feeling of meaninglessness is the specific form their
unhappiness assumes. It seems that in order to allow for the possibility of
someone living a happy, but meaningless life, and a meaningful, but unhappy
life, we need to assume that meaningfulness is an objective property of one’s
life in the sense that you don’t have to feel
your life to be meaningless or meaningful for it to be meaningless or meaningful, respectively, which is also strange,
because it privileges the third-person perspective over the first-person
perspective: I judge your life to be meaningless, even though
you are not aware of it.)
While
happiness, for Kauppinen, is the final good for passive subjects of
experience, meaningfulness is the final good for active agents (372). Since
we are both, experiencers and agents, the best life for us is one that contains
(a maximum of) both, happiness and meaning. (N.B.: I think
this is an important point: that the passive or experiential side of our being
makes for one sort of good, while the active or agential side makes for
another. However, I am wondering how non-human animals would fit in here. Are
animals not also agents? And if they are, do their lives have to be meaningful,
too, to be truly good? And if an animal’s life cannot be meaningful, nor
meaningless, then perhaps it is not agency as such that generates the
orientation towards meaning as a final good, but rather the ability to look
back and plan ahead, to perceive one’s life as being stretched out in time,
surpassing the needs and rewards of the present moment. Meaningfulness would
then not be the final good for agents,
but the final good for recollectors.)
Kauppinen’s
aim is twofold. He wants to a) convince the reader that meaningfulness is an
important dimension of (human) well-being and b) determine what meaningfulness
actually consists in. His method is to present the reader with contrasting cases
of lives lived (some real, some fictional) and then appeal to our intuitions
regarding which of those lives we think is better, all things considered. The
Argentinian revolutionary Che Guevara’s life for instance may have been happier
(and longer) if he had not fought so passionately against poverty and social
injustice in South America, but it almost certainly would have been (or struck
us as) less meaningful, and maybe for that very reason less good overall (and
hence less worth choosing).
In
order to be meaningful, Kauppinen suggests, a life must have a certain
narrative shape. Whether a moment or period in my life is meaningful or not
depends not only on what is happening during that period, but also on what
happened before and what will happen later. Meaningfulness unfolds gradually
over time and is thus, if I understand Kauppinen correctly, ultimately a
property of a life considered as a whole.
In other words, my life now is, properly speaking, neither meaningful nor
meaningless. My life now may well contribute to the overall meaning of my life
(which can be more or less meaningful), but not because it is in itself
meaningful, but because it helps create the narrative shape that makes (or
perhaps better: will have made) my life as a whole meaningful. Meaning is not
additive, which means that a life’s (degree of) meaningfulness cannot be
determined by adding up all the meaningful bits or periods in it (and possibly
subtracting all meaningless or “anti-meaningful” bits, as Campbell and Nyholm
have suggested).
So
what exactly makes a life meaningful? Kauppinen lists a series of key features,
which, when present in somebody’s life, makes it appropriate for them to feel a
certain pride and joy, and appropriate for us to admire and feel inspired by
them. (N.B.: Kauppinen suggests that we understand meaningfulness primarily in
terms of the appropriateness of these feelings: the prouder the agent should
feel about their life and the more admiration we should feel for them, the more
meaningful their life has been. Yet since their appropriateness depends
entirely on the presence of those alleged key features of a meaningful life, I
don’t quite see why we should not focus directly on them. The suggested “fitting
attitude analysis” seems an unnecessary detour.) Key features of a meaningful
life are: that the goals pursued are objectively valuable, that pursuing those
goals challenges the agent’s abilities, that nobody else can replace the agent
in their pursuit, that the goals are pursued with some degree of success, that
success is lasting rather than fleeting, and, perhaps most importantly, that
the agent’s life “forms a coherent whole”, meaning that “past efforts increase
the success of future goal-setting, goal-seeking, and goal-reaching” (346). Because
it is so much goal-focussed, Kauppinen calls this particular conception of
meaningfulness teleological. The view
is summed up in the formula “life is ideally meaningful when challenging
efforts lead to lasting successes.” (346) If good things happen to us, this is
good, but it is even better (namely in terms of meaningfulness) if we had to work hard to make them happen, and the
harder we had to work to get them, the better (more meaningful) our lives are. Furthermore,
to get what we want is good, but it is even better if what we want is good (i.e. worthy of being wanted), and the better
what we want is, the better our lives are. It is even better still if what we
get will last, and the longer it
lasts the better our lives are.
Meaningfulness,
for Kauppinen comes in degrees. Our lives are always more or less meaningful. When
we call a life simply meaningful (or meaningless), then what we actually mean
is that it is more meaningful (or less
meaningful) than the average life, just as when we call someone “tall” what we
actually mean is that they are taller than a contextually determined standard
of comparison, e.g., tall for a five-year old boy, but not tall for a five-year
old elephant. (N.B.: It seems to me, though, that the predicate “tall” adheres
to a different logic than the predicate “meaningful”: while it is impossible
that everyone is tall, it does not seem impossible for every life to be
meaningful, not even maximally meaningful.)
Now,
as others have noticed before, the sequence of events matters for how good we
think a life is. A life that starts out badly, but then gets better (happier),
is considered better (more worth having) than a life which starts out very
well, but then eventually goes downhill. All other things being equal, we would
rather have a happy ending than a happy beginning. The hedonic shape of life matters.
However, Kauppinen notes, there is more to the narrative shape of life than just the sequence of events. Thus an
upward trajectory in life seems more valuable when it is the result of hard
work than if it results from sheer luck. Even a life eventually ending in
failure can be better than a life that ends in bliss, if what precedes the
failure is a sustained effort to achieve something really good and important, and
the bliss, in contrast, comes unearned and unconnected to the achievement of objectively
valuable goals. Noble failure makes for a more meaningful life than sheer luck.
(N.B.: But does it really? How reliable are our intuitions here? Is it really
better for me to fail in my pursuit
of the truly good than to succeed in my pursuit of minor or false goods such as
wealth or fame? Good how exactly? Good in the sense of making my life more
meaningful, but what exactly does that
mean? When we call a life “more meaningful”, are we then really saying more than
Mill did when he called certain pleasures “higher”?)
Kauppinen
holds that meaningfulness is an objective quality of lives: “Just as a food can
be unhealthy for a person even if she thinks it is healthy, a life can be meaningless
for someone even if she thinks it is meaningful.” (356) However, as far as I
can see he does not attempt to provide an argument for this claim. What is
important for him is that we understand meaning in terms of narrative shape. “A
meaningless life is one that is not going anywhere or moving forward.” (357)
Every life has a narrative structure, a plot, he argues (drawing on Aristotle’s
Poetics as a major inspiration), thereby
suggesting that the better the plot is, the better our lives are. (N.B.: The analogy
is initially attractive, but ultimately misleading. A good plot does not always
make for a good life. The story of Oedipus as related by Sophocles has a very convincing
narrative structure, a good plot, and but we would hardly want to say that
Oedipus’s life must therefore have been a good one. In judging the quality of a
life by its narrative qualities we adopt an aesthetic
perspective, which may not be appropriate at all. It is once again a third-person
perspective, a look at a life from the outside, which ignores what it is actually
like to live that life. That a life “is not going anywhere or moving forward” sounds
suspiciously like the complaint of a bored spectator who needs some juicy
action, a rape or a murder perhaps, to sustain their interest. Of course that
is not what Kauppinen has in mind. What he wants a life to have is not really,
as he suggests, a good plot, but in fact an edifying
one, which is not the same thing at all.)
A
good (i.e. meaningful) life plot, for Kauppinen, requires, above anything else,
coherence. Coherence is meant to integrate
all the other key features of a meaningful life mentioned above: “A life is the
more Coherent the more that later activities are positively informed by earlier
activities with respect to goal-setting (the agent’s goals are more valuable
than they would otherwise be), goal-seeking (the agent exercises her capacities
more effectively and/or is more irreplaceable), and/or goal-reaching (the agent
is more successful).” (368) A good, meaningful life is not so much one in which
every single ‘chapter’ is better than the last, but one whose coherence increases
over time. In order for a life to be meaningful, its chapters need to “build on
each other” (which seems to mean that they sustain and reinforce an upward
trajectory). Apparently, however, our life story can have chapters added to it even
after our death, which may then affect the extent to which our lives have been
meaningful. “Since narrative significance of an event can change even after one’s
death, the meaningfulness of a life may be influenced posthumously. What if
Martin Luther King’s campaigns eventually turn out to have led to catastrophic
consequences for African-Americans? Shall we think of his life as having been
as meaningful, or to have been as good for him as we now do?” (374, footnote) Perhaps
not. It is a bit odd, though, to think that we can never be sure how good or
meaningful a life has really been, not even when it is over and we know everything
there is to know about it. Nobody can foresee the long-term consequences of
their actions. And there is no temporal limit to the effects of our actions. Also,
how can something that happens in, say, a thousand years, long after I died, even
if it results in part from my actions now, make my life any better or worse
than it is now? Doesn’t that require some kind of backward causation?