We used to think that
we humans were free and the machines we constructed determined and unfree. But
this is no longer so. Today, in a curious contortion, we are the ones who appear
unfree, and the machines enjoy the freedom that we lack. Increasingly, we think
of ourselves as being shackled by our own nature, which, we believe, has not
changed very much, if at all, since the stone age. (And aren’t we indeed
constantly being told by proponents of human enhancement that the forces of
evolution have shaped us for a world that no longer exists and that in order to
catch up with the world we have created we need to recreate ourselves?) It is
our physical body that, in our own perception, makes us unfree, that ties us to
the past and makes us unfit for the future (and indeed the present). From the
perspective of the machines, human nature is nothing but a nuisance:
“conservative, unprogressive, antiquated, irrevisable, a dead weight in the
rise of the machines”. We could achieve so much more if it weren’t for us and
our defective nature. We see ourselves, as Anders puts it, as the saboteurs of
our own achievements, and we are no longer willing to put up with this. So
something needs to be done: we have to find a way to become more machine-like,
to mould ourselves as we now mould things to assimilate them to our needs and
wants. Our Promethean shame makes us embrace and promote the idea of “human
engineering”, which now appears as something that we owe both to our machines
and to ourselves. After all, we wouldn’t want to be judged a disappointment by
our betters. In relation to our machines we are like children, and growing up,
in this new interpretation of Schiller’s “education of humankind”, means
leaving behind our being human. (Compare Nick Bostrom’s “Why I Want to be
Posthuman When I Grow Up”).
Machines are our
heroes. We yearn to be like them. We see ourselves as “scandalous
non-machines”. Yet machines always have a certain purpose. They are highly
specialised. Human engineering aims at making the human more specialised, at
perfecting a particular ability or capacity to which the human is a mere
appendix, at best tolerated, but no longer of central importance. Thus the
superhuman that human engineering is meant to create is at the same time a
subhuman.
This sounds familiar.
Similar concerns have been raised by Leon Kass. Yet Anders denies that he is
what today we are used to call a bioconservative (he uses the term
“metaphysical conservative”). The point is not that everything that is, is good
simply because it is (or that human nature is good and should remain what it is
simply because it is our nature) – which would be an untenable position –, but
rather that we are willing to change ourselves for the sake of our machines,
that we measure ourselves by their standards, instead of our own, and that, in
doing this, we limit or even relinquish our own freedom. The aspiring human
engineer may well suffer from hubris (as a common objection has it), but he
also suffers from misplaced humility, which is not a contradiction. “The ‘human
engineer is in fact both: arrogant and
self-deprecating, hubristic and humble.
His attitude is arrogated self-abasement
and hubristic humility.”
So when we compare
ourselves to machines, in what way exactly do we find ourselves wanting? One
of the gravest defects seems to be our perishability. We grow old, we die. In
comparison, the things that we create seem to be immortal, at least potentially
so, because very often when they are not it is because we want them to stop working after a certain period of time (so that
more products can be sold). But even those things are immortal in the sense
that they can always be duplicated and replaced. Our products partake in a new
version of immortality: “industrial re-incarnation”. They have a serial
existence. This light bulb or washing
machine may give up its ghost after a few years, but then we can easily get a
new one that is exactly like the old one, or at least one that does exactly the
same job, if not a better one. Their very reproducibility and replaceability
guarantees their immortality. How lucky they are! We on the other hand, their
creators, go bad very quickly and we cannot be replaced. How shameful that is,
how unbearable! Again, something needs to be done. We feel that it cannot, it should not stay like this. (And indeed,
isn’t that what some life extension enthusiasts imagine we will achieve in the
future? Mind-uploading, for instance, to a computer or to a new body, is the
achievement of immortality by making the body replaceable. Others envisage a
periodical cleansing of the mind of all memories to prevent mental ageing and
the boredom of an overly prolonged existence, which creates a different kind of
serial existence.)
Anders’s great insight
is that the human enhancement project is motivated by shame. We are ashamed of
our body, our physical nature, our mere-humanness, our vulnerability and
perishability, and not despite the
fact that none of this is our fault, but precisely because it is (or has been for a long time) beyond our control and
not the result of a conscious decision. It is the very givenness of our nature
that we resent (which explains why Michael Sandel’s argument from giftedness is
so often ridiculed and received with so much hostility by proponents of radical
human enhancement.) It is the fact that we cannot do anything about it that we
are ashamed of. It belies our claims of autonomy, freedom and control. That is
also the reason why we tend to be ashamed of our sexuality. Sex is a “pudendum”
precisely because it makes us lose control and voices our dependency. It shows
us in the grip of nature, of that which lies beyond and before us, and reminds
us that the “I” (the individual in control of herself) is a rather fragile
construction on the back of a powerful “It” (the nature that controls the
doings of the self). And we don’t like that one bit. So what we are trying to
do is regain control over ourselves, and that means to gain control also, and
perhaps even primarily, over our sexuality, without realising that the only
thing we can hope to achieve by this is that we manage to replace one It by
another: the natural It of the body by the artificial It of the machine.
the best English language explanation of my Uncle Gunther work. You are a real "cultural whisperer" who makes his theories accessible.
ReplyDeletethanks
david michaelis