In
his 2005 paper “Ethics and Intuitions” (The
Journal of Ethics 9: 331-352), which I recently reread, the Australian
philosopher and ethicist Peter Singer sets out to “argue that recent research
in neuroscience gives us new and powerful reasons for taking a critical stance
toward common intuitions” (332). The argument follows an argumentative pattern
that I have noticed is increasingly being used by ethicists today, especially
those of a broadly utilitarian persuasion: some science or another is said to
present us with indubitable facts that clearly show some of our commonly held
moral convictions to be wrong, unfounded, or simply not worth holding on to. In
Singer’s case, the scientific findings that he builds his case on are the
results of measuring test subjects’ brain activity through functional magnetic
resonance imaging (fMRI) while confronting them with trolley problems and
asking them what the right thing to do in such situations was. Unsurprisingly,
it turned out that people are generally more reluctant to get involved in
“personal violations” than in “impersonal violations” in order to achieve a
certain morally desirable outcome. If all that needs to be done to save five
people on a railroad track who are about to be crushed by an oncoming trolley
is to throw a switch that redirects
the trolley to a different track where it will kill only one person (who would
otherwise remain unharmed), most people are prepared to say that one should do
it. If, however, the five people can only be saved by pushing a stranger with sufficient mass and weight to stop the
trolley on the track, then most test subjects say that this would be wrong,
even though the outcome (one life is sacrificed to save five others) is exactly
the same. So in the first case they judge like good utilitarians, while in the
second they don’t. The question is why. Neuroscience provides the answer: while
in the first, “impersonal”, case those areas in the brain that are associated
with the emotions show less activity than the areas associated with cognition,
the opposite happens in the second, “personal”, case. Also, those few people
who thought it was right to push the
stranger onto the tracks showed more cognitive brain activity than emotional
brain activity. It did, however, take them longer to come to a decision,
indicating that they, too, first had to overcome an instinctive negative
emotional reaction to the idea of personally harming people.
Now
I can see at least three problems with this argument. First, contrary to what
Singer suggests, the fact that humans used to live in small groups and that
because of the short range of their weapons all killing was necessarily
personal does nothing at all to explain why most people in our society are
reluctant to regard personally killing someone as morally permissible.
Especially not when it comes to strangers. On the contrary, if it is correct
that all violence had to be up-close and personal (i.e. “by hitting, pushing,
strangling, or using a stick or stone as a club”), and if we can assume, which
I think we can, that such violence was not uncommon, especially between those
small groups who, after all, had to compete for scarce resources, then
believing in the formative power of our evolutionary heritage should lead us to
expect people to be rather unconcerned
about inflicting mortal harm on strangers. It is hard to see what evolutionary
purpose a reluctance to kill strangers could have had 50,000 years ago. So the
whole evolutionary explanation of our emotional reaction in the trolley case
scenario is nothing but pseudo-scientific hogwash.
Secondly,
it may be true that “from the point of the Universe” nobody’s good is of more
importance than the good of any other, but that is because from the point of
the Universe nobody’s good is of any
importance at all. This is the perfectly reasonable conclusion drawn by the
psychopath who entirely lacks the instinctive emotional responses that ordinary
people have to inflicting harm on others. Singer mentions the psychopath in
passing when he describes the reaction of those who judged that pushing the
stranger off the bridge was the right thing to do. Even those more rational test subjects, he
points out, had to struggle with their emotions and ultimately judged the case
“in spite of their emotions”. Anyone would, “unless they were psychopaths”
(341). But since Singer argues that those emotional inhibitions, and indeed all
non-rational moral intuitions, are misplaced and ought to be ignored or
discarded, it is difficult to avoid the conclusion that the ideal moral
reasoner is in their mental constitution rather like a psychopath. Singer seems
to sense this himself when, in a curious move towards the end of his paper, he,
once again citing Sidgwick in his support, warns us from praising “people who are capable of pushing someone off a
footbridge in these circumstances” (350) because that might encourage them to
“do it on other occasions when it does not save more lives than it costs”. This
is clearly a form of the slippery slope argument that is occasionally employed
by utilitarians, but I find it difficult to get my head around it. The slippery
slope argument may have some plausibility when we consider acts that are just a
bit wrong or bad and that may easily pave the way for acts that gradually
become worse. You start with one little theft or lie or act of bullying, add
another, and soon you have created a habit that runs out of control, especially
if you receive some encouragement. But why on earth should we expect that being
encouraged to do the right thing (and
praise surely is a form of encouragement) should lead people to do bad things (such as morally unjustified
killing sprees)? Unless of course there is something already deeply wrong with
someone who is capable of doing that supposedly right thing.
Finally,
even though Singer briefly addresses the genetic fallacy in his paper, denying
that he commits one, his argument seems to me a paradigmatic case of such a
fallacy. The fact that the specific way we look at the world and judge what is
good and bad, right and wrong, has its origin in our human nature - which has
been shaped by our evolutionary history and generally circumstances beyond our
control that conceivably might have been different and, if they had, might have
left us with a different nature - in no way discredits it. If it did, then we
would be left with nothing at all that we could rely on, because the way we
reason is just as much rooted in what we have grown to be as the way we feel.
There is no view from nowhere, and the universe couldn’t care less whether we
live or die, or how many live or die. Singer claims that a normative ethical
theory may reject all of our moral
intuitions “and still be superior to other normative theories that better
matched our moral judgments” (345). I don’t think such a theory would be
desirable, or useful, or indeed possible. Ethical theory cannot ignore who and
what we are. It must refer back to our nature, which includes our moral nature.
For better or worse, there is no escape from our way of looking at the world. Trying to get away from this, to
leave our human perspective behind, is not “a way forward” (349), but a fool’s
errand. For what leads to moral scepticism is not, as Singer claims (351), the acknowledgment of our grown nature, but
on the contrary its denial.
No comments:
Post a Comment