Nine
years after Better Never to Have Been
(Oxford University Press 2006), David Benatar has published yet another book about
the harm of coming into existence: Debating
Procreation. Is It Wrong to Reproduce? (Oxford University Press 2015).
Roughly half of the book is written by Benatar, the other half by David
Wasserman who rejects the anti-natalism defended by Benatar and others (Matty
Hayry and Valentine Shiffrin), mostly on the grounds that life is, for various
reasons, not as bad as they depict it, and wrestles with some philosophical
procreation problems of his own. The title of the book is slightly misleading
because there is no real debate between the two authors. Benatar says his bit,
then Wasserman says his, and that’s it. No real dialogue takes place. I will
here focus, once again, on Benatar’s position.
Life
cannot have been very good for Benatar this past decade because he still
believes (or professes to believe) that we would all be better off if we had
never been born and that our parents have inflicted serious harm on us by
allowing us to come into existence. His argument is basically the same,
although he now puts more emphasis on the existential risks that we expose our
children to by bringing them into the world, which may be read as a tacit
acknowledgement that maybe not all
lives are so bad that they are not really worth starting. Even if this were so,
he now argues, for each and every child there is always a non-negligible risk of ending up with a really
miserable life. It may not be likely, but certainly possible. And since we
shouldn’t be playing Russian roulette with our children’s lives (65), we
shouldn’t procreate. Benatar now also fully appropriates the misanthropic argument that he only
alluded to in his previous book on the subject: humans are really so prone to
doing so much damage to each other, to animals, and to the environment, that
the world would be a much better place if we weren’t around. (Maybe so, but I
don’t think we should be giving up on us just yet.) Whatever we may think of
this argument, the fact that Benatar makes so much of it in this new book
clearly shows that his main concern is not primarily theoretical (i.e. to establish the truth of the claim that
existence is always harmful), but practical
(i.e. to convince us that it is always wrong to reproduce). However, the
theoretical claim that existence is always harmful for the one whose existence
it is still constitutes the foundation of his anti-natal position, and it seems
to me that the argument he presents in support of this claim presents the
greatest philosophical challenge to those who, like me, are unwilling to accept
his practical conclusion. So this argument – the (axiological) asymmetry
argument - needs to be dealt with.
What
the asymmetry argument seeks to establish is that “even if there were more good
than bad, the presence of any bad
would be sufficient for coming into existence to be a harm. Because every life
includes some bad, coming into existence is always a harm.” (18) This
supposedly follows from the fact that while it is bad to cause harm (or more
precisely to allow harm to exist), it is not bad not to cause benefit (not to
allow benefit to exist). While the absence of harm is good, the absence of
benefit is neither good nor bad, i.e. “not bad”. (23) For this reason, no
amount of good in a possible future life can outbalance even the slightest harm
in it. This axiological asymmetry between harm and benefit explains why (as
most people would acknowledge) “we have a duty to avoid bringing into existence
people who would lead miserable lives”, but “no duty to bring into existence
those who would lead happy lives.” (25). Similarly, while we may well regret
the suffering of existing people in remote places, we do not regret the absence
of happy people on, say, Mars.
Benatar
finds the axiological asymmetry thesis not only true, but “clearly true”.
Moreover, he accuses those who reject it of “moral callousness” and “moral
insensitivity” (27). So by daring not to accept the thesis we would reveal not
only our essential blockheadedness - because we would allow our truth-tracking
reasoning abilities to be compromised by “powerful biological drives with deep
evolutionary roots” (11), but also our bad moral character. Let’s give it a try
anyway, at the risk of being found wanting both intellectually and morally. Is
the axiological asymmetry thesis obviously true? I think not. In fact, I think
it is false.
Here
is why: we neither have a moral obligation to bring new people into the world,
nor do we have a moral obligation not to bring new people into the world, or
more precisely we don’t have such an obligation to the possible people that could be in the world if we brought
them into it. We may have moral obligations to already existing people, or also
people that are going to exist
independent of our decision to procreate or not to procreate. If, for instance,
we think that the world suffers from overpopulation, then we may conclude that
it would be wrong for us to add to the problem by bringing even more people
into the world. Likewise, if society suffers from a lack of children, we may find that it is our duty to do our bit to
alleviate the problem by reproducing. Or if we knew that our child is likely to
be a very bad person who will cause a lot of harm to others, we may also feel
that we have a moral duty not to have that child. Likewise, if we knew that our
child would be likely to do a lot of good, then we may conclude that we should
reproduce. But generally speaking it is neither wrong (morally prohibited) nor right (morally required) to reproduce. Instead, it is,
in the absence of particular circumstances that speak against or for
reproduction here and now, merely permissible.
Now if we do decide to reproduce, then there will be new people whose existence
we have caused, and we do have moral obligations to them, just as we have moral
obligations to any other person that exists or is going to exist (such as
future generations of people, whose identity is not defined, but who we can
reasonably be sure will exist). If we know that the child that we are going to
have is likely to have a bad life full of suffering, then we may justly be
accused of having caused harm to that child by allowing it to have such a bad
existence (and the greater the harm the more difficult it becomes to justify
our decision to them). Likewise, if we know that the child we are going to have
is likely to have a life that lacks most of the pleasures, satisfied desires,
or benefits that we feel constitutes a good life, then we may also be accused of having caused harm to
that child. In both cases the child that we would have harmed is not the possible child, but the actual child that will exist if we
decide to bring it into the world. The presence of pain (or more generally any
kind of harm), and the absence of pleasure (or any kind of benefit) is equally
bad for that child and may serve as a good (moral) reason for us to abstain
from procreation. It is thus not the
case that while the absence of pain is good, the absence of pleasure is merely
not bad. The one is as bad as the other (especially as the absence of goods is
generally a cause of suffering). While neither harms a possible child, both
harm any actual child that will result from our decision to procreate.
So
why is it generally thought to be wrong to bring a child into existence that
(we know or can reasonably assume) will have a miserable life, but not wrong not to bring a child into existence that
is likely to have a very happy life? And why are we concerned about the bad in
the lives of existing people, but not about the good lives that could exist if we had created them? Does that not imply that the absence of
suffering is good and the absence of pleasure is not bad (i.e. neither bad nor
good)? No, it does not. It merely implies that any moral obligation we may have
is always an obligation to existing people, and never to merely possible
people. If (!) we are going to
reproduce, we should be reasonably sure that the life that results from our
decision is a reasonably good one. A reasonably good life is one that has
sufficient access to life’s goods and is sufficiently devoid of life’s harms.
If we know it is not going to be a reasonably good life, then we should abstain
from reproducing. If we know it is, then we are free to reproduce, meaning that the quality of our future child’s
life does not constitute a moral reason against
reproduction. What it does not mean
is that we have a moral reason for
reproduction.
Now
it may be the case that it is (in an
impersonal sense) better for there to be no world at all rather than a world
that is filled with suffering. But if we accept this possibility (which is not
easy to make sense of, but nonetheless doesn’t strike me as completely absurd),
then it may, on the same grounds, also be better for there to be a world filled
with goods (be they pleasures or something more objective) rather than no world
at all. (We may also feel that a world like ours, in which there is life and
sentience and reflection, is, in some unspecified sense, better than a world in
which none of this exists.) Then the absence of pleasures would be just as bad
as the presence of suffering, or if not just
as bad, then at least also bad. But
we are not in the business of creating worlds. This is not a decision we are
ever going to make, because the world already exists, and it exists with us in
it. What we should be concerned with is whether the lives we create are going
to be good or bad. A good life requires no justification (and creating it is
therefore permissible), while a bad life does
require justification (and creating it is, to the extent that a justification
cannot be given, impermissible).
This
is all very much common sense and does not require any commitment to a
fundamental axiological asymmetry between harm and benefit, or the existence of
impersonal harms and the non-existence of impersonal benefits.
Now,
I could leave it at that, but there’s one more thing about this new book that I
find worth mentioning, namely the now explicit
(albeit partial) endorsement of the transhumanist worldview (lending support to
my view that we are currently experiencing a “transhumanization” of our culture,
which includes our intellectual culture)[1].
Here is what Benatar writes in support of his claim that our lives are actually
much worse than we commonly recognize:
“The
sad truth, however, is that, on the spectrum from no knowledge and no
understanding to omniscience, even the cleverest, best educated humans are much
closer to the unfortunate end of the spectrum. There are billions more things
we do not know or understand than we do know and understand. If knowledge
really is a good thing and we have so little of it, our lives are not going
very well in this regard. Similarly, we consider longevity to be a good thing
(at least if the life is above a minimum quality threshold). Yet even the
longest human lives are fleeting. If we think that longevity is a good thing
then a life of a thousand years (in full vigor) would be much better than a
life of eighty or ninety years (especially where the last few decades are years
of decline and decrepitude). Ninety is much closer to one than it is to a
thousand. It is even more distant from two or three or more thousand. If, all
things being equal, longer lives are better than shorter ones, human lives do
not fare at all.” (52)
“Human
lives would (…) be immensely better if we lived for many thousands of years in
good health and if we were much wiser, cleverer, and morally better than we
are.” (53)
“To
prefer a human life to a better life suggests a distracting sentimentality
about humanity. It is to think that it is more important to be human than to
have a better quality of life” (58)
“Not
all optimists fetishize humanity. Among the advocates of human enhancement are
those who envisage and welcome the project of a ‘post-human’ future – a future
in which humans have been so enhanced (physically, mentally, and morally) that
they are no longer recognizably human. These advocates of transhumanism think
it is much more important to improve the quality of life than for the enhanced
future beings to be human. While there are many who object to the wisdom and
morality of seeking such enhancements, I am not among those categorically
opposed to technological enhancements.” (60)
Where
Benatar disagrees with transhumanism is mostly with regard to the optimistic
expectation that with such enhancements our lives will soon be good enough.
Enhanced posthuman lives will certainly be much better, but that doesn’t
necessarily mean that they will be good (60). Why? Because “we would still die and
we would still have vastly more ignorance than knowledge” (62), to which a
truly dedicated transhumanist may well respond: Just wait, have faith, we are
already working on it. Immortality and omniscience might be difficult to
achieve, but eventually, if we try hard enough, we may well figure it out. And
then, when we are for all intents and purposes like Gods, even Benatar will
have to agree that our lives are now, finally, worth living.
[1] Cf. Michael Hauskeller, “A Cure
for Humanity? The Transhumanisation of Culture”, Trans-Humanities 8/3 (2015): 131-147. A pre-print version can be
accessed here: https://www.academia.edu/9517910/A_Cure_for_Humanity_The_Transhumanisation_of_Culture
No comments:
Post a Comment