It
is often said that life is absurd. However, it is not always clear what exactly
we mean by that. What, if anything, makes it absurd, and why do we think, as we
seem to do, that life’s being absurd is something we should rightly worry about?
Perhaps life is absurd and that is
actually a good thing. This is what
Thomas Nagel argues in a paper on the topic, published in 1971.[1]
Nagel
begins his investigation by ruling out the usual suspects. What makes life
absurd is not the fact that what
matters to us now will most likely not matter anymore at some time in the future
(say, in a million years), because we have no good reason to think that the things
that matter to us now would matter more or would only really matter if they also mattered in the future. Also, if what
happens now does not matter in the future, then surely what happens in the
future does not matter now. Consequently, it does not matter now whether what
matters now will also matter in the future.
Neither
is what makes life absurd the fact that we will die, or the fact that we are
very small and insignificant when compared to the enormous size of the universe.
If our life is absurd (i.e. meaningless) now, then it would also be absurd if
we lived considerably longer or forever, or if we were actually big enough to
fill the universe. Nor is life absurd because it will be cut off at some point
and in that sense does not lead anywhere. What we do in life does in fact lead
to many things in life. Why should it
have to lead to something that is no longer part of our life? The chain of
justifications (‘I do this in order to achieve that’) needs to come to an end somewhere, and there is no reason why it
should not come to an end within our given life span.
From
this it does, of course, not follow that life is not absurd. What follows is
merely that if life is absurd, it
must be something else that makes it so. Nagel suggests that we normally call a
situation absurd if there is a “conspicuous discrepancy between pretension or aspiration
and reality” (31). You are being knighted and your pants fall down, that kind
of thing. Accordingly, life as a whole would be absurd (for each one of us) if
there were an inevitable clash
between our pretensions as human beings and reality (or what we know about it).
Now there is indeed such a clash, namely between our inability to take our life
other than seriously and our inability,
as thinking beings, not to understand the ultimate arbitrariness of everything we do. Among the animals, only humans
have the ability to look at their own lives from, as it were, the outside, as
mere spectators, or sub specie
aeternitatis. If we adopt this “view from nowhere” (as Nagel shall later
call it), then we realize that everything that is important to us is only important because we happen to be
the kind of creature that we are. If we were different, then different things
would matter to us. Nothing matters in itself. It is all contingent, and in
that sense arbitrary. When we look at our lives from that perspective it seems
rather ludicrous how seriously we take it all. And yet, seriously we do take
it. We have to carry on with our lives and to continue to treat things as
important that from an impartial spectator’s point of view are anything but. (I
know it does not really matter
whether I get that promotion or not, but knowing this does not change the fact
that it still matters to me.) This inevitable
conflict of perspectives is where absurdity lies: that we can be deeply
involved in our lives and, at the
same time and without undermining or diminishing our involvement in any way,
realize that if we had been “put together” (35) differently we could just as
well be involved in something else, or in nothing at all. In this respect, our
sense of the absurd resembles epistemological scepticism: despite understanding
perfectly well that I have no grounds to be certain about anything (for
instance the existence of an external world or other minds), I cannot help continuing
to act as if I was certain. Or rather, I am
certain, although I know that, rationally speaking, I shouldn’t. Similarly, I
take my life seriously, although I know that I have no rational grounds to do
so.
However,
something changes when we cultivate (rather than suppress) the external view on
our lives: our seriousness is not gone (which would in fact be disastrous), but
it is now “laced with irony”. (37) Should we regret this? For Nagel, the
absurdity of (our) life is actually a good thing and not something we should bemoan
or try to escape from. It is most definitely no reason to despair. Remember, it
is only because we can look at our
lives from the outside that life can appear absurd to us. We don’t really discover it to be absurd. If Nagel is
right, then our lives are not absurd prior
to our realizing this. The absurdity consists
in the conflicting viewpoints. That is why the life of an animal is never
absurd, precisely because it cannot be absurd for it. For an animal, say a mouse, life is never absurd because he
lacks that crucial impartial perspective. He lacks the “self-consciousness and
self-transcendence that would enable him to see that he is only a mouse.” (38) Yet
is he better off because his life is not absurd? No. The animal’s life is not
absurd, says Nagel, but it is not meaningful either. In fact, at the end of his
paper Nagel comes very close to suggesting that it is actually the very fact
that we have a sense of the absurdity of our lives that makes our lives
meaningful. “I would argue”, he writes, “that absurdity is one of the most
human things about us: a manifestation of our most advanced and interesting
characteristics.” Our sense of the absurd is in fact “a way of perceiving our
true situation” and a result of our “capacity to transcend ourselves in thought”
(39). So nothing to worry about. (And anyway, Nagel rather glibly concludes, if
nothing matters, then it does not, or should not, matter that nothing matters
either.)
COMMENTARY:
I
am wondering whether Nagel’s analysis of our sense that life is absurd does not
rely rather too heavily on a redefinition of the absurd. Nagel’s absurd does
not seem to be the absurd that people tend to be concerned about. When he
begins his analysis he occasionally uses the term ‘meaningless’ synonymously with
‘absurd’, but when he reaches his conclusion, the absurd has mutated into
something else that can no longer be equated with meaninglessness. No wonder then
that Nagel does not find the absurd particularly bothersome. All it does is
invite us to adopt a slightly ironical, moderately detached attitude towards
life. We still take life seriously, but perhaps not that seriously anymore. We have distanced ourselves slightly from
our individual persona, have gained a little freedom from ourselves and can now
meet the world with a little more equanimity. That is all very useful and
liberating, I’m sure. However, it does not really address the existential
concerns that people sometimes have, about whether, when all is said and done, life
is really worth all the trouble. Why bother if in the end it will all be for
nothing? The worry that nothing might really matter is an existential worry, or, in Kierkegaard’s sense, an ethical worry. In contrast, Nagel’s
absurd is purely aesthetic, more pleasurable
than horrifying. It is indeed the product of the view from nowhere, the absurd
of a pure spectator. Never mind that I am
that spectator and what I am looking at is my own life, which I cannot help taking seriously. It is still from the
spectator’s perspective that it appears absurd to me. It is the place where I
can laugh about my struggles, where death is simply the end of a story that has
been told before and will be told again, many, many times. But the absurd that
bothers and alienates us, which might even drive us into despair, is something
that is perceived not from the viewpoint of the spectator, but from the
viewpoint of the one who actually lives that life. And who lives it here and
now and only this once. Nagel’s absurd is harmless, even edifying, because it
is perceived from the outside. It
invites us to see the comical side of things. Yet there is also an absurd that
is perceived from the inside, and
that is a very different thing, something that does not liberate us from our
natural obsession with ourselves, our inborn parochialism, but that instead
rips a hole into our world and threatens to rob us of our sanity. Here be lions
and dragons, here be cold and dark and emptiness. It is a different, far less
congenial kind of absurd, one that is more akin to the absurd of Lovecraft and
Ligotti than to that of Nagel.
One
more thing: the notion of the absurd is very much associated with the French
philosopher Albert Camus. Nagel mentions him, but only briefly and rather
disparagingly at the end of his paper, only to accuse him of being a bit too “romantic
and slightly self-pitying” (39). Instead of happily embracing the ironic
detachment that the absurd can and should give rise to, Camus asked us to respond
to the absurd with defiance, by “shaking a fist at the world”. This, however,
is at best only partly true and a bit of a caricature. The absurd, for Camus,
also rests on a discrepancy, but not between an internal and an external view,
but between human hopes and desires on the one hand, and the unresponsiveness and
indifference of the universe on the other. But what Camus thinks of as the
appropriate response to this discrepancy amounts to more than just shaking one’s
fist at the world. It is, rather, a determination not to accept the
indifference with which the universe looks back at us, and to resist this indifference by not adding
to it. We defy the absurd by insisting that it matters what we do, by making them matter, by caring about what happens and what is
being done to other people, and by acting accordingly. We thus create, little
by little, a different universe, one that does care, at least in part, because
we do. In short, Camus’ absurd prompts us to care more, whereas Nagel’s absurd
prompts us to care less.
[1] Thomas Nagel, “The Absurd”. Originally
published in the Journal of Philosophy
68/20 (1971): 716-727. Reprinted in Life,
Death and Meaning. Key Philosophical Readings on the Big Questions, ed.
David Benatar, Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield 2004, 29-40 (which is the
version I have been using).
I agree with your last paragraph, that Nagel caricature's Camus position. In the end I don't think they're positions are so far apart. Sisyphus knows that nothing matters, but that that doesn't matter anyway. In fact Camus recommends Sisyphus face his life with irony, when he meditates an his way back down the hill. But in his project he gives meaning at least to the here and now.
ReplyDeleteThanks, Steven. Yes, he does indeed. In case you are interested, I recently wrote a book chapter on Camus, the first draft of which can be found here: https://www.academia.edu/29792475/Albert_Camus_and_the_Benign_Indifference_of_the_World
ReplyDeletei'm working on my Philo essay, you helped me a ton!
ReplyDelete