In 1886, the French
symbolist Auguste Villiers de l’Isle-Adam published The
Future Eve (L’Ève Future), which gives a new twist to the story of
Pygmalion and the artificial woman that he creates for himself out of disgust
for the impurity of all real women.
The
Future Eve tells the story of the inventor Thomas Edison (a fictionalised version of the real Edison), who
has been experimenting with the creation of a female android for some time when
an English friend of his, Lord Ewald, asks him for help. Ewald has fallen in
love with an exceedingly beautiful woman, an aspiring actress called Alicia
Clary, who is in fact the exact likeness of the Venus de Milo exhibited in the
Louvre. In other words, she looks as if that statue had come alive. Unfortunately,
however, Ewald finds to his dismay that Alicia’s beautiful, goddess-like
appearance is not matched by her character. Outside and inside are at odds.
What her body promises, her soul cannot fulfil: “her inner self was in absolute
contradiction to her beautiful form. Her beauty was quite foreign to her words,
her conversation appeared out of place in such a voice.” It is almost as if
“this woman has strayed by accident into the form of the goddess – that this
body does not belong to her”.
So what exactly makes
Alicia so unworthy of her beautiful exterior? There are various things that
Ewald dislikes about her: she doesn’t sufficiently appreciate her own beauty
and makes no attempt to live up to it. She has no “lofty aspirations” or “high
ideals”. She sings to make a living, rather than for the sheer beauty of it. She
eats heartily (i.e. not at all like a lady). She is interested in money. She
has no principles. She tells him without embarrassment about an unhappy love
affair that she has gone through, unaware that such openness is likely to
“destroy all the sympathy and admiration” the high-minded Lord might have had
for her. She is not exactly foolish, but she is silly. She has talent, but no
genius, is a virtuoso, but no true artist. She doesn’t like Wagner (whose music,
admired by Villiers de l’Isle-Adam, is “just a lot of bangs, just noise” to her) and
when her admirer takes her to the Louvre and alerts her to her likeness with a
particular marble statue, she exclaims: “Yes, that’s me, except that I have not
lost my arms, and I am much more aristocratic-looking.” I’m sure most people
would agree that there is nothing really repulsive about her character. She is
just an average woman, not too bright, certainly no intellectual, a bit selfish
or self-absorbed perhaps, but her flaws are nothing out of the ordinary,
nothing that she does not have in common with millions of other people. For
Ewald, however, this is exactly the problem: she is too common. The contrast
between her divine features and her all-too-human character is unbearable. A
woman who looks like that should not have any flaws. She should be perfect, ethereal,
and the fact that she is not constitutes a moral outrage, a sacrilege, a
violation of nature and reason. She is a living contradiction, a monster really:
“Imagine a commonplace goddess! I
have come to the conclusion that all physiological laws were overthrown in this
living, hybrid phenomenon.” Ewald concludes his damning assessment of Alicia’s
character by proclaiming that he “cannot love a woman who has no soul.” So
Alicia, because she is disappointingly average and has no lofty aspirations
(and also because she does not seem to be inclined to be as devoted to Ewald as
he is to her and as he imagines he deserves it), is denied a soul. In Ewald’s
eyes, she is merely a beautiful, but essentially hollow, form, which makes him
cry out in desperation: “Oh, who could put a Soul into that body!”
Fortunately, Ewald
couldn’t have come to a better place to ask that question: “’I can!’ exclaimed
Edison. ‘I shall put a wonderful soul into that beautiful body!’” The
irony here, probably not intended by the author, is of course that it is not,
as we would expect, the statue (or
the android that is eventually going to replace Alicia) that is said to be
without a soul, but the living, breathing
woman who has the temerity of deciding for herself what is important to
her, what kind of life she wants to live, and whom she wants to love and whom
she does not. That real and very much alive woman can only be denied a soul
because the word “soul” is here just the name for an allegedly ideal condition,
a mode of existence that has transcended all the apparent pettiness and
coarseness of our common human concerns and that is entirely devoted to the
higher realms, whatever that means exactly. Conveniently this mode of existence
coincides with a complete submission under the wishes and desires of the man
who wants to see her thus transformed. And it this kind of “soul” that the professor promises to provide:
“Twenty-one days from now, at this same hour, Alicia Clary will stand before
you, not only transformed, not merely a delightful companion, with a mind of
the highest intellectual type, but reclothed in a phase of immortality.” She
will no longer be a woman, but “an angel”, “not the cold Reality, but the
Ideal.”
Edison then sets
out to work and gradually transforms the prototype android that he had already
created (an entity or rather “an electro-magnetic thing”, “a being of limbo”)
into a perfect duplicate of Alicia (with soft, caressable flesh and skin),
except that the new Alicia (or Hadaly, as Edison calls her), the “future
Eve” of the story’s title, has a “soul”, meaning that she meets all the
expectations that a male member of genteel society might have when looking for
a suitable female companion. Tellingly, the creation of a soul for Alicia is
described as an eliminative process. It is in reality the creation of an
absence: her “selfish frivolity” is ‘annihilated’, her “insipid animality” ‘destroyed’.
The new Alicia may even be “less conscious of herself”, perhaps not conscious
at all, but “what does that matter” if her behaviour is “suggestive of
impressions a thousand times more beautiful, more noble, more elevated”? I take
this to mean that it is not even necessary for the new Alicia to actually feel
or think anything at all, as long as she (or her creator) manages to make
people believe that she does. Thus the
desired “soul” is located exclusively in her appearance, in what the new Alicia
says and does. What she feels or not feels is entirely irrelevant – she might
just as well not feel anything at all. It is only the expression of certain sentiments (love, devotion, tenderness) that
her lover needs, and that expression of a sentiment is to all intents and
purposes the sentiment itself. That is why Ewald, as the professor assures him,
will actually feel less alone with the new, artificial Alicia (even if she should
turn out to be “less conscious”), than he does presently with the real one (who
quite naturally is not focussed entirely on her lover and does not live for him
only). “I do not think that it will be a very great loss if Hadaly is lacking
the kind of a conscience that her model has – do you? It will be to her
advantage not to have it, at least, in your eyes, since Miss Clary’s
conscience seems to be deplorable, a blot on the masterpiece. The conscience of
a worldly woman – bah!”
However, occasionally
it is suggested in the text that the new Alicia most likely will have feelings
of some sort. Thus Edison warns Lord Ewald that when he and she are
going to take the ship back to England, it is best if she spends the journey in
a coffin-like box (just like Count Dracula in Bram Stoker’s novel, which was to
be published 11 years later, in 1897). Why? Because her “serenity should not be
ruffled; she should not be humiliated by the sight of the defective organisms
of her human companions.” So she is expected to be capable of feeling
humiliated, though it is unclear why she should feel humiliated (instead of proud) by the fact that she is more perfect
than ordinary, “defective” human beings – unless, on that occasion, she
identifies with humanity. What is suggested here seems to be a curious reversal
of Gunther Anders’s Promethean Shame: instead of us humans feeling ashamed about
our own inferiority when we compare ourselves to the wonderful machines that we
have created, it is here the machine that feels humiliated (perhaps on behalf
of us humans, who don’t know yet how inferior we actually are?).
In any case the new
Alicia will be a creature that is completely under the control of her lover,
who can activate and deactivate her and direct her movements and speech by
pushing certain buttons cleverly hidden on her anatomy. “She is loyal to only
one person, she will recognize one only – her master.” So her newly gained “soul”
shows itself primarily in a loss of freedom and autonomy. She is no longer her
own master, which is just as it should be. And she will not only be exactly what
it says on the tin, but she will also stay that way. Deplorably, every real
woman ultimately proves illusive. She can never live up to what her beauty
promises. What we see in her is just an illusion, facilitated by “cosmetics,
creams, powders, and beauty patches”. Strip her of this, and what remains is an
“old witch”, a grotesque imitation of the ideal that she pretended to be. In
any case, she will soon lose all her charms to middle age. So “why not build a
woman who should be just the thing that we wanted her to be”, one who is always
beautiful by her very nature, and beautiful forever? This would definitely
solve the problem that the over-curious young man in Swift’s “The Lady’s
Dressing Room” after his look behind the scenes struggles with, namely how to
live with the fact that no woman is a goddess. The answer suggested by Villiers
de l’Isle-Adam is simple: don’t live with it. Make your very own Goddess
instead. And why not? Every man, it is suggested, has in fact a natural right to his own goddess. If the plan succeeds,
then Man’s “lost paradise” will be restored to him, life will be as it should
have been all along, and he will once again be master of the situation, or in
short, “the dominator”. The new Alicia, who is the real Alicia, that is Alicia as she was meant to be, will always say what her lover wants to hear. “Her
conscious utterance will no longer be the negation of yours, but will become
the semblance of the soul that responds to your melancholy. You will be able to
evoke in her the radiant reality of your exclusive love, without fearing, this
time, lest she repudiate your dream. Her words will never disappoint your
hopes. They will always be sublime (...). Here, at least, you will have no fear
of being misunderstood, as with the living woman”.
In the end, Edison delivers what he has promised, and it turns out that he has not
promised too much. Lord Ewald is entirely satisfied with the outcome: “The
false Alicia was more perfect, more natural, than the living personage.” What a
strange thing to say: that the android, an artificial thing, is not only more
perfect, but more natural than the
woman on which it was modelled. But then again, for Villiers de l’Isle-Adam, it is only the
perfect that is natural, only the ideal that is (completely) real. What we
commonly take for real is just a bad, defective copy of the ideal, which is, in
a Platonic sense, the really real. The machine allows us to introduce the world
of ideas into the world of appearance, to merge the two worlds into one, to
bring heaven onto earth. Thus the (dead) machine is more real than the living
human who is nothing but a “phantom” in comparison.
The new Alicia knows no
sickness or death, and she never changes, which also means that she will never
stop loving Ewald as he wishes to be loved (and don’t we all wish to be loved
unconditionally and eternally on some level?). She will always stay devoted to
him, and to him only: “I shall be the woman of your dreams – all that you would
have me be.” The author seems to fully endorse this idea. Yet towards the end
of the novel, Villiers de l’Isle-Adam, almost despite himself, nonetheless gives voice to a
certain unease that sheds doubt on the whole project of replacing admittedly
flawed, annoyingly wilful, and constitutionally unpredictable human beings with
flawless, completely reliable and always obliging machines. “Her heart”, we
learn, “will never change, because she has no heart.” Can we really want that?
Isn’t that too high a price to pay for the illusion of eternal love? L’Isle
Adam seems to sense this himself when he lets his Edison reflect on the
greatness of his achievement after Ewald and his future Eve have left him to
live happily ever after in England (only for her to perish in a fire soon
afterwards): “This is the first time that science has been able to prove that
she can cure man – of love.”
So love is seen as a
problem, or more precisely a disease, and technology provides the cure, not by
facilitating the fulfilment of love, but instead by getting rid of it
altogether. If that is what truly happens here, then that would also explain a
remark that Edison made earlier in the novel and which, at the time, seems
rather out of character. When Ewald has to decide whether he really wants the
professor to go ahead and create a new, purified Alicia for him, he is initially
undecided and asks Edison what he would do, and he replies: “I would
blow out my brains first”, which is a very odd thing to say really, given that
it was his idea in the first place and that at all other times he seems
absolutely committed to the project.
No comments:
Post a Comment